Rethinking Context: Realisation, Instantiation, And Individuation In Systemic Functional Linguistics
A Meticulous Review Of Doran, Martin and Herrington (2024)
24 November 2024
23 November 2024
Confusing Mode With Hyper-New
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 194):
As we noted above, the opening sentence predicts that the following text will talk about archaea. This is done through participant tracking: the entity archaea is presented, and then referred to (in bold above) as this full branch of living beings and as archaea twice. In addition this entity is classified as not just some arcane microbe, an entire domain of life, and a whole living domain. The final reference to archaea occurs in the final clause archaea are now classified as a distinct, third domain of living creatures, that functions as a Hyper-New synthesising the point of the excerpt. This Hyper-New demarcates the boundary between this excerpt and the following text. But between the opening and closing sentences, the participant chain and classification (amongst other things), functions to sustain the chunk of information and make clear that we are still focusing in some sense on the same stretch of information.
Reviewer Comments:
To be clear, in SFL Theory, mode is the part language is playing in terms of the culture. Chunks of information, on the other hand, are language, as too is Martin's discourse semantic function of hyper-New, which is his rebranding of the notion of 'paragraph summary' in writing pedagogy.
21 November 2024
Confusing Mode With Grammar And Discourse Semantics
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 193-4):
Mukherjee (2022: 68–69) draws on these resources in order to tell the story of the discovery of archaea we saw above. The excerpt we will explore follows reports of two of the branches of life: eukaryotes and prokaryotes. It begins by introducing the third branch archaea at the beginning of a new paragraph by saying:And now the third branch: archaea (Mukherjee 2022: 68).Before looking at the whole excerpt, we can note that this sentence functions as a clear demarcation of information from the previous chunks about eukaryotes and prokaryotes.
From the perspective of PERIODICITY and THEME (Halliday and Matthiessen 2014; Martin and Rose 2007), it puts forward a Hyper-Theme that predicts what is to come (a stretch about archaea) and draws on both a marked and textual Theme (And now) in order to shift the text (Fries 1995).
From the perspective of IDENTIFICATION (Martin 1992), it both presents a new participant that has not yet previously been mentioned (archaea) and splits an established participant chain (via the third branch) – making clear that there has been a first and second branch, and that this is a separate third branch.
And finally, from the perspective of CONNEXION (Halliday and Hasan 1976; Martin 1992), the sentence-initial internal addition conjunction And signals a new stretch of language being connected to the previous.
Three sets of textually oriented systems, then – PERIODICITY, IDENTIFICATION, and INTERNAL CONNEXION – work together to indicate that there is a new chunk of information coming up.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] To be clear, in SFL Theory, mode is the part language is playing in terms of the culture. Chunks of information, on the other hand, are language, as too are Halliday's grammatical system of THEME, and Martin's discourse semantic systems of PERIODICITY, IDENTIFICATION and CONNEXION.
19 November 2024
Confusing Mode With The Textual Language That Realises It
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 193):
The model proposed here conceptualises mode as a resource for organising information. As with the models for tenor and field, it does so in a way that aims to make the links between mode and the textual metafunction clear, while at the same time being able to connect with patterns of genre. Under this tentative model, texts can be organised into chunks of information, by demarcating boundaries or sustaining the text’s flow. These options occur within a system called JUNCTURE.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] To be clear, here again the authors aim to make the links between context (mode) and language (textual meaning) clear by misinterpreting context as the language that realises it.
[2] As previously explained, from the perspective of SFL Theory, Martin's stratum of genre is a confusion of text type (register), mode and semantics (text structure). However, in any case, it will be seen that the authors do not make any connections with "patterns of genre".
[3] To be clear, the organisation of texts is the organisation of language, not context.
17 November 2024
Misunderstanding Instantiation
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 192):
The ability to both render positions and orient them in relation to people and other positions offers a means of building large networks of meaning that are organised not through ideational configurations (i.e. through field), but through rhetorical relations (what in LCT Maton 2014 calls an axiological constellation). That is, it allows us to map sets of interpersonal values and how they are oriented to different people and communities (Doran 2020a, 2020b, 2024). As noted above, this is done in a way that maintains the connection between tenor and the interpersonal metafunction.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] As previously demonstrated, the authors' 'rendering' is a rebranding of speech function, interpersonal semantics, misunderstood as tenor.
[2] This has instantiation backwards. It is the networks of interpersonal meaning that provide the ability to "render positions" and so on, in texts.
[3] To be clear, the way the authors "maintain the connection between tenor and the interpersonal metafunction" is by rebranding an interpersonal semantic system as tenor.
15 November 2024
Misrepresenting Language As Tenor
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 191):
Although we cannot explore tenor resources in more detail here, the above texts also illustrate how positions can be sourced to different people, and arranged in relation to each other – such as when Mukherjee (2022) draws on but (a resource for countering) to oppose the initial reactions to Woese’s work (sourced to Many prominent biologists, functioning as the Appraiser) to the current feelings (sourced to us):Many prominent biologists ridiculed or simply ignored Woese’s work […]. But decades later, we have largely accepted, validated, and vindicated his theory.
Reviewer Comments:
Again, this is language, not tenor. The tenor is 'who is taking part': author-reader relations.
13 November 2024
Misunderstanding Context-Metafunction Resonance
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 190):
This example shows that a wide range of positions can be supported or rejected not just in dialogue, but in monologue as well. In addition, it illustrates that for this negotiation, it is not enough to just focus on attitude or engagement (or for dialogue, exchange); rather one must look at how these resources all together realise general patterns of support or rejection. Importantly, this is done almost entirely through interpersonal systems, allowing us to maintain the context/metafunction resonance between tenor and the interpersonal metafunction.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] Again, the example shows that the authors confuse interpersonal language (negotiation, attitude, engagement) with tenor. The tenor of the situation of the example is the relation of author to reader.
[2] Again, this demonstrates that the authors misunderstand the notion of context-metafunction resonance. Here they interpret it as tenor being realised by the interpersonal metafunction of language. As previously explained in a quote by Halliday, the relation between tenor and interpersonal language is that tenor decides the range of interpersonal meaning. This means that interpersonal selections vary with tenor, not that ideational and textual selections are not implicated in the realisation of tenor. But it is the interpersonal meaning — not the ideational or textual meaning — that identifies the tenor.
11 November 2024
Confusing Tenor With Interpersonal Semantics
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 190):
Mukherjee (2022: 68–69) uses this resource [ENGAGEMENT and ATTITUDE] when recounting the discovery of archæa – the third main branch of organisms. In the example below, the positions that are being rendered (supported or rejected) are underlined, and the resources that render them are in italics for support and bold for reject.
[2] Regarding the authors' analysis, 'the positions that are being rendered' are said to be:
- we had misclassified not just some arcane microbe
- war
- Taxonomy wasn't just missing the point, it was missing a whole living domain.
- Archaea were not "almost like" bacteria or "almost like" eukaryotes.
- Woese's work
- his theory
the resources said to render support for the positions are:
- spirited
- accepted, validated and vindicated
- mis-
- not
- lonely, bitter war that left him ragged at the edges
- wasn't
- missing
- not
- ridiculed or simply ignored
09 November 2024
Mistaking Interpersonal Semantics For Tenor
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 190):
Importantly, these resources [tendering and rendering] do not just occur in dialogue, but allow for different positions to be negotiated in monologue. This typically draws on resources of ENGAGEMENT and ATTITUDE, as different positions are put forward, supported, or rejected. Indeed, we saw an example of this above where the teacher said They’re not condensed. Here they drew on the negative not (disclaim: deny in Martin and White’s ENGAGEMENT system 2005), to reject the position that they are condensed.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] As previously explained, tendering and rendering are rebrandings of initiating and responding moves in the exchange structures that realise Halliday's interpersonal semantic system of SPEECH FUNCTION, misunderstood by the authors as tenor.
[2] To be clear, the claim here is that the interpersonal semantic systems of ENGAGEMENT and ATTITUDE are "drawn on" in tendering and rendering. However, because the authors avoid the technical theoretical term 'realise', it is not clear whether these two remain semantic systems, or whether they are also part of the authors' general misinterpretation of tenor as the semantic systems that realise it.
07 November 2024
Rebranding Speech Functions (Semantics) As Tendering And Rendering (Tenor) [2]
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 189-90):
But in practice, tendering and rendering are often done together. This occurs when in response to what one person puts forward, someone else puts forward something that only implies their support or rejection. An adapted example from our classroom illustrates this when the teacher and a student go back and forth as to what is on a diagram:
Here, the student puts forward that the green things are spindle fibres. The teacher rejects this, not by saying explicitly that they are wrong, but by tendering an alternative suggestion (that they are microtubules). However the student is not convinced, and so counters by arguing they’re not moving – both rejecting the teacher’s characterisation and tendering a reason for it – a move which the teacher once more rejects by tendering an alternative position (they’re condensing).
Reviewer Comments:
To be clear, the tenor of this situation — 'who is taking part' — is student and teacher. What they say is language, not context. The tendering and rendering in their dialogue are speech functions in an exchange. Each response in an exchange potentially serves as an initiating move for the next response. The speech functions of the moves in the exchange are as follows:
- The first move in the exchange is a statement, rebranded here as 'tender'.
- As a response, the second move in the exchange is a contradiction, rebranded here as 'render: reject'.
- As an initiating move, it is a statement, rebranded here as 'tender'.
- As a response, the third move in the exchange is a contradiction, rebranded here as 'render: reject'.
- As an initiating move, it is a statement, rebranded here as 'tender'.
- As a response, the fourth move in the exchange is a contradiction, rebranded here as 'render: reject'.
- As an initiating move for a future response, it is a statement, rebranded here as 'tender'.
05 November 2024
Rebranding Speech Functions (Semantics) As Tendering And Rendering (Tenor) [1]
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 189):
Under this model, people can tender meanings to be engaged with, or they can render meanings that have been put forward. For example in the classroom we have looked at, following the teacher asking the students what is inside the centrosome, a student tenders an answer that the teacher then renders by supporting it (by both repeating the answer and using positive attitude Right, Sweet). This follows a prompt from the teacher “Inside the centrosome is…again?” An arrow shows the direction of the rendering.
In other instances, the teacher rejects students’ suggestions. In the following, they do this by using the Modal Adjunct No, plus they’re not condensed yet:
These instances illustrate simple instances where rendering cleanly follows tendering.
Reviewer Comments:
- the teacher initiates the exchange with a question,
- the student makes the expected response, an answer, and
- the teacher makes the expected response, an acknowledgement.
- the student initiates the exchange with a statement, and
- the teacher makes the discretionary response, a contradiction.
03 November 2024
Misunderstanding Tenor And Context-Metafunction Resonance
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 188-9):
As Poynton (1990) has shown, variables in terms of contact (how close one is to another person) and status (the degree of ‘equality’ or ‘hierarchy’ in the relationship) can in fact be linked to manifestations of language having to do with how reciprocal the sets of choices are between people (status) and how many meanings can be shared (contact).
As we will discuss in Section 3.2 below, these choices are not restricted to the interpersonal metafunction, but in fact impinge upon choices in all metafunctions. Thus while these dimensions can be more clearly associated with patterns of language, we once more face the issue that this approach erodes the metafunction/context resonance upon which SFL’s model of language and context is constructed. Accordingly, we will propose below that these dimensions be interpreted as principles of instantiation, rather than as tenor options within the realisation hierarchy.
… Doran et al. (2024) propose a new model of tenor as a resource for enacting social relations. This model works to make clear the links between tenor and the interpersonal systems of language, and so maintain SFL’s context/metafunction resonance, as well as providing a map of resources that are used across situations to negotiate social relations and realise distinct genres.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] Here the authors extend their misunderstanding of 'context-metafunction resonance' from field to tenor. To be clear, the notion of context-metaphor resonance does not mean that a tenor variable only has implications for interpersonal choices. As Halliday explained, tenor decides the range of interpersonal choices. What this means is that a specific tenor is identified, that is, distinguished from others, by the interpersonal choices that realise it, rather than by ideational or textual choices.
[2] To be clear, this new model of tenor misunderstands tenor as the interpersonal language that realises it. That is, in terms of symbolic abstraction, it misconstrues the Value as the Token. And confusing levels cannot 'make clear the links between tenor and the interpersonal systems of language'.
01 November 2024
Misunderstanding Field As The Language That Realises It
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 186-7):
Finally, both activities and taxonomies can be described in terms of potentially gradable properties. For example, when Mukherjee (2022: 68) describes bacteria, he does so by describing their characteristics (in bold) and the place they live (spatiotemporal properties underlined):The abundance and resilience of bacteria stagger the mind. Some live in oceanic thermal vents where the water reaches near boiling temperature; they could easily thrive inside a steaming kettle. Some prosper within stomach acid. Yet others live, with seemingly equal ease, in the coldest places on earth, where the land freezes into packed, impenetrable tundra for ten months of the year. They are autonomous, mobile, communicative, and reproductive. (Mukherjee 2022: 68)As this excerpt shows, these properties can be graded as being higher or lower (known as arrayed), such as the coldest place on earth and near boiling temperature. Although not specified here, arrayed properties are often gauged by being measured or quantified (e.g. 133.61 °F, 100 °C).
Taxonomy, activity and property make up the basic perspectives on field and offer complementary construals of phenomena. But as we have seen, they do not build their meaning in isolation. Their meanings regularly interrelate with each other, as we saw above where the classification taxonomy of types of organism was based upon their differing compositional taxonomies.
In addition, each of these perspectives on phenomena can be reconstrued in terms of the other. For example, the teacher names the activity of a cell dividing into two identical daughter cells as mitosis.
By naming it in this way, the teacher reconstrues the activity of a single cell dividing into two identical daughter cells as an item – mitosis; or what we call an itemised activity. This allows mitosis to function as an item and be related to other items – for exemple by establishing a classification taxonomy of types of mitosis (e.g. orthomitosis, pleuromitosis, extranuclear mitosis, intranuclear mitosis, closed mitosis, open mitosis, etc.). At the same time, mitosis can function as an activity and be sequenced with other activities as, say, moments within the cell cycle, along with interphase, telophase, and cytokinesis. Properties can also be reconstrued – for example when Mukherjee (2022) described bacteria as in terms of their abundance and resilience (thereby reconstruing the properties abundant and resilient as itemised properties).
Reconstruals and interrelations such as these allow for increasingly expansive and integrated construals of phenomena. They provide rich resources to build knowledge of the world around us and to map and explain highly complex fields (Doran and Martin 2021; see also Carr 2023; Chen 2024). Together with the basic relations of field – activity, property, and taxonomy – they also link closely with ideational meanings within language (see Hao 2020),which for SFL theory, allows us to maintain ideational register/metafunction resonance between language and context.
Reviewer Comments:
To be clear, this all misunderstands field — what's happening in terms of the culture — as the ideational language that realises field.
30 October 2024
Misunderstanding Field As A Semantic Sequence That Realises It
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 185-6):
A complementary perspective on field is a dynamic perspective that construes phenomena as a set of activities. For example, in our classroom the teacher explains mitosis as an activity where a single cell divides into two daughter cells (underlined).
This example presents mitosis as a single activity – what we can call an unmomented activity. Alternatively, activities can be divided into a series of moments. When Mukherjee (2022: 99) visualises mitosis, he presents a caption that explains it in terms of its moments – what we call a momented activity. After describing that the chromosomes are initially present in loose threadlike forms in the nucleus, he explains:
Then the threads tighten into dense bundles. The nuclear membrane dissolves, and the chromosomes separate into two sides of the cell, as if drawn by some forces. When they’ve fully separated […] the cell splits, generating two new cells. (Mukherjee 2022: 99)The activities that Mukherjee (2022) describes are as follows (where ^ indicates a sequence):The threads tighten into dense bundles^The nuclear membrane dissolves^The chromosomes separate into two sides of the cell, as if drawn by some forces^They (the chromosomes) fully separate^The cell splits^Two new cells are generated(Mukherjee 2022: 99)This presents a complementary view to the static one focused on items – it outlines a dynamic unfolding of events. These activities are interconnected with the items and taxonomies that are involved in them. In this instance, the cell splits due to activities associated with two of its parts: the nuclear membrane dissolving and the chromosomes separating.
28 October 2024
Misunderstanding Field As A Lexical Hyponomy That Realises It
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 184, 185):
Alternatively, items can be related in terms of type and sub-type into a classification taxonomy. Mukherjee (2022: 67–69) draws on this when he lays out the diversity of cells that occur on Earth:
This stretch of text is organised around three subtypes of organism (in bold above), for which he also gives some examples. We can visualise this classification taxonomy as in Figure 3.Every cell on Earth – which is to say every unit of every living being – belongs to one of three entirely distinctive domains, or branches of living organism. The first branch comprises bacteria: single-celled organisms that are surrounded by a cell membrane, lack particular cellular structures found in animal and plant cells, and possess other structures that are unique to them […] We think of them as pathogens – batonella, pneuomococcus, salmonella – because a few of them cause disease […]. We – you and me – inhabit a second branch, or domain, called eukaryotes. The word eukaryote is a technicality: it refers to the idea that our cells, and the cells of animals, fungi, and plants, contain a special structure called a nucleus (karyon, or “kernel” in Greek). This nucleus, as we will soon learn, is a storage site for chromosomes. Bacteria lack nuclei and are called prokaryotes – that is, “before nucleii” […] And now the third branch: archaea. It may be the single most startling fact in the history of taxonomy that this full branch of living beings remained undiscovered until about fifty years ago […] they lack the defining features of the other two domains. (Mukherjee 2022: 67–69)
26 October 2024
Misunderstanding Field As A Lexical Meronomy That Realises It
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 183-4):
Beginning with the static perspective, this involves viewing fields as sets of items that can be arranged into taxonomies. One type of taxonomic relation is that of composition – where items are arranged into a part-whole relations. For example, in a classroom lesson in cell biology, the teacher at one stage reads from the textbook:
Here, the teacher explains that animal cell centrosomes are composed of two centrioles, which in turn include nine groups of three microtubules. We can visualise this as a compositional taxonomy as in Figure 2.
24 October 2024
Misunderstanding Field As The Ideational Language That Realises It
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 183):
Accordingly, in this section we will outline field as a resource for construing phenomena. This perspective emphasises the resonance between field and the ideational metafunction in language, as well as offering tools that can link upwards with genre. The model presented here is that of Doran and Martin (2021). Under this model, phenomena can be construed dynamically as a set of activities oriented to some social action or they can be construed statically as relations among items.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] As previously explained, and as will be seen, this misunderstands field, 'what is happening' in terms of the culture, as the ideational language that realises it.
[2] To be clear, the "resonance" here derives from misinterpreting field as language.
[3] It will be seen that the 'dynamic' construals are semantic: sequences, and that the 'static' construals are lexical: meronymic and hyponymic taxonomies.
22 October 2024
Deconstructing The Authors' Notion Of Field, Tenor, And Mode As Guiding Principles For Instantiation
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 182):
In essence, what we are proposing in this paper is that given the significant expansion in the architecture of SFL in recent decades – in terms of more clearly distinguishing the hierarchies of realisation, instantiation, and individuation – we have an opportunity to rethink our understanding of field, tenor, and mode. In particular, we will suggest that given the wide-range of things field, tenor, and mode have been asked to account for, a fruitful avenue for exploration is to consider them from multiple angles. Rather than just considering them as components of a single stratum within the hierarchy of realisation, we can also consider them in terms of guiding principles for the probabilistic co-selection and arrangement of choices in instantiation (linking more closely to Halliday’s ‘register’ and Gregory’s [and our] ‘diatype’). We can also consider them from the perspective of individuation as arenas of variation, contestation, and collaboration (though this latter perspective will only briefly be touched upon in this paper). In short, field, tenor, and mode are asked to do a lot in SFL theory, and we propose it is time to give SFL the theoretical space it needs to do so.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] This is a mere pretext. Realisation has been part of the theory since its inception more than 50 years ago, instantiation has been clearly distinguished from realisation for about 40 years, and individuation is not explored in this paper.
[2] This demonstrates an ignorance of the architecture of language already proposed by SFL Theory. To be clear, Halliday's register is a point of variation on the cline of instantiation, at the level of language content, from system (potential) to text (instance). Registers differ by instantiation probabilities, with each register realising a situation type, which is a point of variation on the cline of instantiation, at the level of context, from culture (potential) to situation (instance).
That is, the probabilistic instantiation that distinguishes registers varies with the contextual configuration (Hasan) of field, tenor and mode variables that define a situation type. It is in this sense that field, tenor and mode are already "guiding principles" for the instantiation of the linguistic features that distinguish registers. Situation type, however, does not feature in the authors' model.
20 October 2024
The Two Basic Misunderstandings From Which This Paper Proceeds
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 182):
In this paper we take another step by reconstruing field, tenor, and mode as resources for making meaning (as opposed to classifications of kinds of context) – with a view to designing networks that strengthen the correlation of intrinsic with extrinsic functionality (Section 3 below). In addition we will offer an interpretation of permeability from the perspective of instantiation – with respect to principles for coupling choices across metafunctions which we refer to as mass, association, and presence (see Section 4 below).
Reviewer Comments:
[1] As previously explained, this is the first major misunderstanding of SFL Theory in this paper: misunderstanding the context of meaning making as the language that makes meaning.
[2] As previously explained, this is the second major misunderstanding of SFL Theory in this paper: misunderstanding 'context-metafunction resonance' as an exclusive metafunctional relation between context and language.
[3] To be clear, 'permeability' refers to Hasan's observation that field, tenor and mode are partially interdependent. Hasan (1999: 244):
The contextual parameters – field, tenor and mode – are not, to use Bernstein’s (1975) terminology, three strongly classified domains, each with a clear-cut boundary of its own: they are in fact permeable. What choices are made in field is relevant to some extent to the choices in tenor and in mode.
This is, of course, the same for language. For example, a choice in the system of THEME (textual) is relevant to choices in MOOD (interpersonal) and TRANSITIVITY (experiential).
18 October 2024
Misunderstanding Context-Metafunction Resonance
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 180):
This division of labour distributes the wide range of phenomena a model of social context must conceptualise if it is to engage closely with language across four context variables instead of three, and helps ensure that each component of field, tenor, and mode is not doing so much work that it no longer matches up with the internal metafunctional organisation of language.²
² Matthiessen et al. (2022: Figure 7.9) make this lack of resonance in their modelling clear in a diagram linking what they consider to be different fields of activity with different areas of grammar “at risk” – implicating ideational, interpersonal, and textual systems, not just ideational ones.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] To be clear, the fourth variable is Martin's genre, which, unlike his register, is not organised according to the three metafunctions. This reflects the fact that genre is a misunderstanding of one metafunction, the textual, as projected onto context as mode.
[2] This misunderstands the metaphor of 'resonance' in the hypothesis of 'contextual-metafunction resonance' (Hasan 2014: 8). As previously explained, the hypothesis is simply that the contextual parameters of field, tenor and mode are identifiable by the ideational, interpersonal and textual choices, respectively, in language (and vice versa).
The authors, on the other hand, misunderstand 'contextual-metafunction resonance' as requiring that the three parameters of context exclusively "match up wth" their respective metafunction of language. This is their second major misunderstanding of theory, and the one that motivates the second half of this paper.
16 October 2024
Misunderstandings Of Mode As Field In SFL
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 180):
Note however that when genre is treated as a supervenient system there are implications for more specific characterisations of field, tenor, and mode.
As far as field is concerned it means that with respect to the modelling of socio-semiotic processes such as enabling, exploring, expounding, reporting, and the like in Matthiessen’s work (e.g. Figure 6.13 in Matthiessen et al. 2008) or the modelling of verbal action such as instructing, planning, narrating, informing, and the like in Hasan’s work (e.g. Figure 3 in Hasan 1999) – both are handled at the stratum of genre, not register (see Martin 1992; Martin and Rose 2008).
Similarly in relation to mode, the modelling of rhetorical ‘modes’ such as expository, didactic, persuasive, descriptive, and the like in Halliday’s work (e.g. Halliday 1978: 143–145) is also handled at the stratum of genre, not register.
Reviewer Comments:
To be clear, as the work of Halliday demonstrates, the work of Matthiessen and Hasan confuses rhetorical modes (the part language is playing in the culture) with field (what's happening in the culture). This can be seen, for example, in Matthiessen's confusion of mode ('the part played by language') with field ('what's happening') in Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 37):
14 October 2024
Clarifying The SFL Model Of Field, Tenor And Mode
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 180):
Turning to register variables, field is concerned with what is going on, tenor addresses who is taking part, and mode deals with the role assigned to language (alongside attendant modalities of communication and behaviour). Halliday (in Halliday and Hasan 1985: 12) provides a little more detail:
field is concerned with “what is happening […] the nature of the social action that is taking place: what is it that the participants are engaged in, in which the language figures as some essential component?” (Halliday and Hasan 1985: 12)
tenor addresses “who is taking part, to the nature of the participants, their statuses and roles, including permanent and temporary relationships of one kind of another […] and the whole cluster of socially significant relationships in which they are involved.” (Halliday and Hasan 1985: 12)
mode deals with “what part the language is playing […] including the channel (is it spoken or written or some combination of the two?)” (Halliday and Hasan 1985: 12)
These general characterisations offer a useful starting point for viewing language in relation to context.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] Importantly, for Halliday and Hasan, and SFL Theory, context is the culture modelled as a semiotic system that is realised as language. So it is important to understand that
- field is 'what is happening' in terms of the culture,
- tenor is 'who is taking part' in terms of the culture, and
- mode is 'what part the language is playing' in terms of the culture.
12 October 2024
Misunderstanding The Realisation Relation Between Context And Language
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 179):
In this model, register is the name of the stratum comprising the contextual variables field, tenor, and mode. This contrasts with Halliday’s use of the term register to refer the skew of probabilities in semantic systems inside language by field, tenor, and mode (e.g. Halliday 1991a, 1991b).
As far as the realisation relationship between the contextual variables field, tenor, and mode and language is concerned (i.e. probabilistic realisation), this difference is purely terminological. Language realises field, tenor, and mode in both models, and field, tenor, and mode choices skew language choices in both models.
The substantive difference in the models revolves around whether or not context is stratified into field/tenor/mode and genre, or only includes field/tenor/mode.¹
¹ As this terminological distinction has often led to confusion, it would perhaps be useful in the model assumed here to use Gregory’s (1967) suggestion of ‘diatype’ for the skewing of probabilities in the systems of language by choices in field, tenor and mode (i.e. Halliday’s register), leaving register as the cover term for field, tenor, and mode.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] This is potentially misleading. For Halliday, and SFL Theory, register is a point of variation on the cline of instantiation of the content plane of language, midway between potential (system) and instance (text). Registers differ from each other in terms of the probabilities of feature instantiation.
[2] This is misleading because it misrepresents the relation between levels of symbolic abstraction, context and language, as causal (enhancing). Importantly, the relation between any two levels of symbolic abstraction is intensive identity (elaborating).
[3] This confuses realisation with instantiation. It is instantiation, the selection of features in logogenesis, that is probabilistic. Realisation is simply the identity relation between any two levels of symbolic abstraction.
[4] This is very misleading indeed, because the difference is considerably more than merely terminological. To take one example, in Halliday's model of context, the cline of instantiation extends from culture (potential) to situation (instance), but neither culture nor situation has a terminological counterpart in Martin's model.
[5] This is not misleading because it is true. But it hints that the second half of this paper is motivated by the authors' intention to refute the criticism of Martin's model of stratified context in The Conception Of Context In Text (Hasan 1995).
10 October 2024
Problems With Context Stratified As Genre Realised By Register
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 179, 180):
The stratified model of context assumed here is outlined in general terms in Figure 1 – where genre is a supervenient system realised through choices in register (after Martin 1992).
… In general terms, genre models context as a system of staged, goal-oriented social processes realised through register, the latter comprising field, tenor, and mode (Martin 1992; Martin and Rose 2008).
Reviewer Comments:
As previously explained, in rebranding context (of culture) as 'genre', Martin (1992) confuses rhetorical mode (context) with text type (language), which is register viewed from the instance pole of the cline of instantiation. So, from the perspective of SFL Theory, in Martin's model,
- genre is mode realised by field tenor and mode;
- genre is register (text type) realised by register (system sub-potential).
08 October 2024
Problems With The Authors' Perspectives On Context
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 178):
In this paper, we draw attention to two key developments since that time that arise from viewing the register variables of field, tenor, and mode from multiple perspectives. These are the perspectives from
(i) realisation, where the register variables field, tenor, and mode are reconstrued as resources for making meaning; and
(ii) instantiation, involving a reconsideration of register from a multifunctional perspective on knowledge building (mass), social relations (association), and context dependency (presence).
Reviewer Comments:
[1] To be clear, from the perspective of realisation, field, tenor and mode are at the level of context, whereas resources for making meaning are at the level of language. In reconstruing context as language, the authors confuse distinct levels of symbolic abstraction. This alone is sufficient to invalidate their model.
[2] To be clear, from the perspective of instantiation, context is the cline from culture (potential) to situation (instance), and field, tenor and mode are the metafunctional perspectives on context. On the other hand, register, from the perspective of instantiation, is a point of variation in language, between system (potential) and text (instance).
[3] To be clear, in taking a 'language-based approach to cognition', SFL models 'knowledge' as meaning. Halliday & Matthiessen (1999: ix-x):
It seems to us that our dialogue is relevant to current debates in cognitive science. In one sense, we are offering it as an alternative to mainstream currents in this area, since we are saying that cognition "is" (that is, can most profitably be modelled as) not thinking but meaning: the "mental" map is in fact a semiotic map, and "cognition" is just a way of talking about language. In modelling knowledge as meaning, we are treating it as a linguistic construct: hence, as something that is construed in the lexicogrammar. Instead of explaining language by reference to cognitive processes, we explain cognition by reference to linguistic processes.
06 October 2024
The Starting Point For This Paper
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 178):
As reviewed in Tann (2017), Martin (2010) outlines an SFL framework for the study of semantic variation organised around three ‘hierarchies’ of meaning – realisation (strata of abstraction), instantiation (cline of generalisation), and individuation (scale of belonging). This is our starting point for this paper.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] This is misleading because it misrepresents these SFL dimensions of language as Martin's framework. To be clear, 'realisation' and 'instantiation' are dimensions in Halliday's original model, and 'individuation' was introduced in the work of Matthiessen.
[2] This seriously misunderstands these three dimensions of language. 'Meaning' refers to the semantic stratum of language, but the three dimensions are also relevant to other strata of language, as well as to context. The error derives from Martin's misunderstanding of 'all strata make meaning', which describes semogenesis (making meaning) not stratification, as 'all strata are meaning'. It will be seen that this fundamental misunderstanding is the basis of the authors' "rethinking" of context from the perspective of realisation.
[3] This seriously misunderstands these three dimensions of language. 'Realisation' is not a hierarchy, but a relation (of symbolic identity) between any two levels of symbolic abstraction, such as between strata or between axes.
Instantiation is not a cline of generalisation, which is the scale of delicacy, but an elaborating relation of class membership between a token (instance) and a type (potential). Halliday & Matthiessen (1999: 144-5) distinguish delicacy, realisation and instantiation as three types of elaboration:
In other words, the elaboration sets up a relationship either of generality (delicacy), of abstraction (realisation), or of token to type (instantiation): see Table 4(4).
And individuation is not a scale of belonging (extension) of meaners, but a cline of differentiation (elaboration) of meaning. However, this dimension is not explored in this paper.
[4] As can be seen from the above, the starting point for this paper involves very serious misunderstandings of SFL theory.
04 October 2024
Misconceiving Context As Language
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 178):
In this paper, we propose a new perspective on modelling field, tenor, and mode in systemic functional linguistics (SFL hereafter). This involves treating each contextual variable as a resource – reconceiving field as a resource for construing phenomena, tenor as a resource for negotiating social relations, and mode as a resource for composing texture. In doing so we outline some of the key implications of this new perspective for SFL’s conception of realisation (as strata of abstraction), instantiation (as a cline of generalisation), and individuation (as a scale of belonging).
For realisation, we argue that it bears critically on the issue of whether or not to adopt a stratified model of context (as register and genre) and the relationship between extrinsic functionality (field, tenor, and mode) and intrinsic functionality (ideational, interpersonal, and textual metafunctions).
For instantiation, we suggest that it bears critically on our modelling of principles for coupling (co-selecting and arranging choices within and across languages and related modalities of communication) – for example mass, presence, and association.
And for individuation, we propose that it bears critically on the perspectives of allocation (i.e. how access to meanings and their uptake is distributed across communities) and affiliation (i.e. how meanings are used to collaborate and struggle, within and between social groups).
Our main concern is to develop a model which improves traction as far as SFL work on language in context is concerned, fully embracing a multimodal perspective on language and related modalities of communication as resources for meaning.
Reviewer Comments:
[1] To be clear, this new perspective confuses the cultural context of language with the language that realises the cultural context. Specifically, the authors misconceive:
- contextual field as the ideational function of language in construing experience as meaning;
- contextual tenor as the interpersonal function of language in enacting social relations as meaning;
- contextual mode as the textual function of language in making discourse relevant to context.
02 October 2024
The "Lack Of Consensus" On Context And Its Relation To Language
Doran, Martin & Herrington (2024: 177):
In spite of decades of research developing a model of language and context, there is little consensus in systemic functional linguistics (SFL) about how context should be modelled and how language and context are related. …
For realisation it bears critically on the issue of whether or not to adopt a stratified model of context (as register and genre) and the relationship between extrinsic functionality (field, tenor, and mode) and intrinsic functionality (ideational, interpersonal, and textual metafunctions).
Reviewer Comments:
[1] To be clear, Halliday originally modelled context as the culture as a semiotic system. He used Hjelmslev's notion of a connotative semiotic to model language as the expression plane of context.
Any lack of consensus on how to model context only arises from the fact that Martin (1992) misunderstood Halliday's model, and that two generations of Martin's students accept Martin's misunderstanding without question.
Martin's misunderstandings of context are examined in great detail in the review of Martin (1992), here, but the confusions can be summarised briefly as follows.
Martin (1992) rebrands context of situation (instance) as register and context of culture (potential) as genre. That is, he misconstrues the relation of instantiation on the plane of context as a relation of realisation between strata on the plane of context.
In rebranding (context of) situation as 'register', Martin misconstrues instances of context as subpotentials of language, registers, that realise situation types. That is, he confuses instances of the stratum that is more abstract than language, context, with a point of variation on the cline of instantiation of language, register.
In rebranding (context of) culture as 'genre', Martin confuses rhetorical mode (context) with text type (language), which is register viewed from the instance pole of the cline of instantiation. The structures proposed for different genres are semantic structures that vary for different text types (language) that realise different rhetorical modes (context).
As this deconstruction demonstrates, Martin's misunderstandings are multidimensional, and are so convoluted that students have little option but to accept them on trust.
[2] As will be seen in the course of this review, the authors devote the second half of this paper to addressing their own misunderstanding of how the contextual parameters of field, tenor and mode are related to the ideational, interpersonal and textual metafunctions of language — what Hasan (2014: 8) terms the hypothesis of 'context-metafunction resonance' (CMR).
To be clear, Halliday (1978: 117) explains his original claim as follows:
In other words, the type of symbolic activity (field) tends to determine the range of meaning as content, language in the observer function (ideational); the role relationships (tenor) tend to determine the range of meaning as participation, language in the intruder function (interpersonal); and the rhetorical channel (mode) tends to determine the range of meaning as texture, language in its relevance to the environment (textual).
That is:
- field (e.g. biology) decides the range of ideational content,
- tenor (e.g. teacher-student) decides the range of interpersonal content, and
- mode (e.g. spoken dialogue) decides the range of textual content.